TutorChase logo
IB DP Philosophy Study Notes

6.1.2 Arguments for the Existence of God

Within the study of philosophy, the justification of a divine entity's existence has always been a profound point of contention. Philosophers have crafted a series of arguments, not empirical proofs, which are designed to support the rationality of believing in a God.

The Ontological Argument

This argument is a priori, meaning it is independent of empirical evidence and instead uses logic and definition to argue for God’s existence.

  • Anselm’s Classical Formulation:
    • Anselm defines God as "that than which nothing greater can be conceived".
    • If God exists merely as an idea, a greater being could be imagined to exist in reality.
    • This would contradict God's definition as the greatest conceivable being.
    • Hence, God must exist not just in the mind but in reality.
  • Plantinga’s Modal Ontological Argument:
    • Alvin Plantinga introduced a contemporary version involving possible worlds.
    • If God exists in some possible world, then God exists in all possible worlds.
    • If God exists in all possible worlds, then God exists in the actual world.
    • If God exists in the actual world, then God exists.
  • Critiques and Defenses:
    • Critics argue that existence is not an attribute that increases greatness (Kant).
    • Defenders propose that the argument doesn't rely on existence as a predicate, but rather on the necessity of God’s existence in a metaphysical sense.

The Cosmological Argument

This argument suggests that everything has a cause, and traces these causes back to a first cause or an unmoved mover—God.

  • Aquinas’ Five Ways:
    • Aquinas proposes multiple proofs, with the first three being cosmological arguments:
      • Argument from Motion: There must be a first mover, set in motion by no other, and this is God.
      • Argument from Causation: There must be a first cause, which itself is uncaused, and this is God.
      • Argument from Contingency: There must be a being that is necessary, whose non-existence is impossible, and this is God.
  • Kalam Cosmological Argument:
    • This medieval Islamic formulation was revitalised by William Lane Craig and argues:
      • Whatever begins to exist has a cause.
      • The universe began to exist.
      • Therefore, the universe must have a cause, which is asserted to be God.
  • Critiques and Defenses:
    • Critiques often question the nature of causality, such as with quantum physics suggesting acausal events.
    • Defenders argue that causality is a rational principle that applies even if not all physical events seem to adhere to it.

The Teleological Argument

The teleological argument claims that the existence of order and design in the universe indicates a designer.

  • William Paley’s Watchmaker Analogy:
    • Paley argues by analogy that just as the complexity of a watch implies a watchmaker, so too the complexity of the universe implies a divine designer.
  • Modern Design Arguments:
    • The complexity of biological systems and the fine-tuning of universal constants suggest intentionality.
    • The argument is bolstered by the improbability of such conditions arising by chance.
  • Critiques and Defenses:
    • Evolutionary theory provides a significant challenge by offering a naturalistic explanation for complexity.
    • Defenders maintain that evolution does not explain the origin of life or the fine-tuning of the universe's laws.

Karma as Proof of God in Nyaya Hindu Thought

In Nyaya philosophy, karma serves as a logical foundation for the existence of God.

  • The Logical Foundation of Karma:
    • The meticulous cause-and-effect of karma implies an overseeing power.
    • Without a divine enforcer, the moral order of karma would be unadministered and arbitrary.
  • God as the Moral Order-keeper:
    • The Nyaya school posits that the existence of a systematic moral order necessitates a divine being who monitors and dispenses karmic justice.
  • Critiques and Defenses:
    • Critics question whether a natural moral order requires a divine being.
    • Nyaya philosophers argue that the consistency and fairness of the karmic system are best explained by a divine intelligence.

Critique and Counter-Critique

Each argument has been both criticised and defended over the centuries.

  • Common Criticisms:
    • The premises of each argument are debated (e.g., why must the universe have a cause?).
    • Logical problems are pointed out (e.g., can the concept of a necessary being be coherent?).
    • Alternative explanations are offered (e.g., the universe might be a brute fact).
  • Defenses:
    • Arguments are refined to address criticisms (e.g., expanding on the nature of causality).
    • Intuition and religious experience are often cited as supplementary evidence.
    • The cumulative case for God’s existence is emphasised over individual arguments.

FAQ

The application of the Ontological Argument to concepts other than God, such as a perfect island or the greatest possible being in a particular category, is known as the 'perfect island' objection. This criticism suggests that if the argument's logic were sound, it could be used to prove the existence of any perfect entity merely by defining it as such. However, proponents of the argument maintain that it uniquely applies to God because God's existence is supposed to be necessary, unlike contingent entities like islands. This specificity does not necessarily weaken the argument but rather delineates the scope within which it is intended to operate.

The Nyaya argument for the existence of God through karma differs from Western moral arguments in that it is not solely grounded on moral intuition or the moral nature of humans but on the logical structure of the moral law as it operates in the universe. Western moral arguments, such as those from Kant, often rely on the existence of a moral law and a moral legislator (God) who makes moral law obligatory. In contrast, the Nyaya argument focuses on karma as an objective, impersonal, and consistent process that maintains moral order. It posits that such an orderly process requires a divine enforcer, making the argument less about moral obligation and more about cosmic justice and order.

The Kalam Cosmological Argument posits that the universe had a beginning, and by implication, it suggests that time itself had a beginning. This is because the argument is based on the premise that an infinite regress of temporal events is impossible. Philosophical theories of time, such as A-theory (which posits a moving present) and B-theory (which sees all points in time as equally real), interpret the beginning of the universe differently. The argument aligns more closely with A-theory, implying that time is dynamic and had a definite starting point, which is consistent with the Big Bang theory.

Quantum physics introduces the concept that, at a subatomic level, events can occur without a discernible cause, known as quantum indeterminacy. This phenomenon suggests that not all events are bound by classical causality. If true, this would challenge the cosmological argument's premise that everything must have a cause. However, some philosophers argue that quantum indeterminacy does not undermine the causality principle at a macroscopic level and that it's inappropriate to extrapolate quantum behaviour to the universe's origin. Additionally, some theists contend that God could be the cause of the universe in a way that transcends physical causality.

The Problem of Evil challenges the Teleological Argument by questioning the benevolence and omnipotence of the purported designer. If the universe is designed with such intricacy and purpose, the existence of evil and suffering seems incompatible with a benevolent God. It raises the question of why an omnipotent and omniscient being would create a world where natural disasters, diseases, and moral evils are present. This issue is particularly potent when considering the seemingly needless suffering in the world that does not appear to serve any greater purpose or design.

Practice Questions

Evaluate the strengths and weaknesses of the Kalam Cosmological Argument for the existence of God.

The Kalam Cosmological Argument is cogent in its simplicity and appeal to empirical intuition; it aligns with the universal experience that effects have causes. It successfully avoids the infinite regress of causes by positing a necessary first cause. However, its major weakness lies in the assumption that the universe began to exist, which may be contested by some cosmological models suggesting an eternal universe. Additionally, even if the argument establishes a cause, it does not necessarily identify that cause with the God of classical theism, thereby leaving some theological implications unaddressed.

Discuss the relevance of Anselm's Ontological Argument in the context of contemporary philosophy of religion.

Anselm's Ontological Argument remains relevant as it challenges the intellect and introduces the concept of God as necessarily existent. Its relevance persists in contemporary debates about the nature of existence and the possibility of conceiving a being than which nothing greater can be conceived. Despite Kant's critique that existence is not a predicate, the argument is still utilised in modern discussions about the nature of necessary existence and possible worlds, as evidenced by Plantinga's reformulation. It illustrates the enduring struggle to rationally articulate the concept of God without empirical evidence.

Hire a tutor

Please fill out the form and we'll find a tutor for you.

1/2
About yourself
Alternatively contact us via
WhatsApp, Phone Call, or Email